The received wisdom of early reviews of the English edition was that the book offered riches in its historical analysis but that its prescription, specifically a progressive annual tax on wealth, was politically unfeasible. I suspect that judgement will prove to be superficial and that the book's lasting legacy may turn out to be its methodological challenge to neoclassical economics on the one hand, and the impetus it gives to institutional reform on the other. Whether either amounts to much will have to be seen. Ultimately, Piketty's political role has been to irrefutably prove that the emperor is stark-bollock naked, rather than open our eyes to a hitherto hidden truth.
Piketty and the canon
Though neoclassical economics makes a fetish of maths, it is is ultimately (like all economics) a species of moral philosophy that makes normative claims. There are three of particular note: that once an economy develops, market forces will lead to a progressive decline in inequality (aka the Kuznets Curve); that the share of national income between capital and labour is constant over time, ruling out any theory of exploitation of one by the other; and that income inequality accurately and proportionately reflects marginal productivity, i.e. just desserts for different labour contributions. Piketty's analysis of historical data contradicts all three claims: after declining over the middle years of the twentieth century, inequality has been increasing since the 1980s; the share of national income going to capital at the expense of labour has also increased; and, outside the exceptional period of 1914-75, the returns to capital have exceeded growth (i.e. productivity).
Piketty concludes "There is no natural, spontaneous process to prevent destabilizing, inegalitarian forces from prevailing permanently". In saying this, he also distinguishes himself from both the pessimists of classical economics, such as Malthus, who envisaged over-population being controlled by famine, and the optimists, such as Smith and Say, who assumed a natural harmony. It is the "destabilising" insights of Ricardo and Marx, in respect of scarcity and accumulation, that Piketty thinks are more relevant to the modern world, though he disagrees with their apocalyptic prognoses, which he ascribes to historical ignorance of the declining importance of land and the increasing impact of technology.
The "inegalitarian forces" he identifies are social, specifically the privileged position of those who receive a return on capital. Consequently, like Keynes before him, Piketty identifies the rentier as the "enemy of democracy". To diminish the rentier we must "take a serious interest in money, its measurement, the facts surrounding it, and its history". He concludes: "Those who have a lot of [money] never fail to defend their interests. Refusing to deal with numbers rarely serves the interests of the least well-off". But his prescriptions, like those of Keynes, are essentially managerialist and institutional - progressive taxation by the state and inter-state cooperation - rather than the democracy of workers' control. This is then essentially a social democratic manifesto. It shows how far the Overton Window has shifted over the last 30 years that an appeal for social justice and democracy should be considered radical.
A touch of class
Though he has simplified the maths that neoclassical economists have routinely used as a veil, Piketty has not entirely removed that veil, hence class is generally obscured by reference to percentiles and deciles. Despite the focus on inequality, and his insistence that economics is properly a subdiscipline of the social sciences, this is not a work of sociology. Indeed, his widely admired use of the fictions of Balzac and Austen, among others, allows him to distance his analysis from the lived reality of the modern world.
That said, Piketty is not wholly oblivious to class. His empirical approach, showing that the growth of "supermanager" incomes is a specific Anglo-Saxon phenomenon and not tied to economic performance, is key to his case that marginal productivity does not explain inequality. He is also aware of the politics, more so than many of his critics on the left concede, noting that this growth correlates with the ideologically-driven decision to lower top rates of income tax in the UK and US in the 1980s, but he doesn't tease out the implication of this in terms of power, namely that any future wealth tax might be discounted through further gross increases in supermanager pay.
I suspect the marginal role given to class and power reflects Piketty's belief that the state is incapable of doing the heavy lifting of advancing greater equality through social investment any more, in large part because it lacks the opportunity and impetus provided by war and reconstruction. In this regard his political analysis is sharp to the point of cynicism. In sceptically answering the question Do educational institutions foster social mobility?, he notes (in reference to the founding of France's Sciences Po after the Paris Commune) that "the upper classes instinctively abandoned idleness and invented meritocracy lest universal suffrage deprive them of everything they owned". Allowing for the anachronistic "meritocracy", that is a sentence that would have not looked out of place in the notebooks of Gramsci.
The long march through the institutions
Piketty's book has little to say about the institutional legacy of Bretton Woods, namely the IMF and World Bank, which emphasises his concern with distribution rather than production and his focus on the developed world. But he is voluble on the European Union, believing that without supra-national coordination at the regional level, taxes on capital cannot be effectively implemented in the age of globalisation. Contrasting the more coercive control of capital in China, he makes the case for a tax as being consistent with European traditions: "The capital tax is the liberal form of capital control and is better suited to Europe's comparative advantage". Similarly, he emphasises the USA's pioneering record in introducing taxes on wealth and high marginal rates of income tax in the twentieth century, implying that the current political aversion to taxation is purely ideological, rather than a permanent cultural feature of the country.
Faced with the flaws of the Euro (a "stateless currency" with essentially arbitrary rules on debt and deficits), Piketty proposes the creation of a budgetary parliament, distinct from the current European Parliament and made up of deputies from the various national parliaments in the Eurozone, that could provide a democratic mandate to pool public debt and collectively manage fiscal and monetary policy. He is firmly on the side of more union: "if we are to regain control of capitalism, we must bet everything on democracy - and in Europe, democracy on a European scale". This provides a potentially popular justification for greater union, far superior to the technocratic case advanced by the political elite.
His argument also gives European politicians retrospective wiggle-room, suggesting that their inadequate response to growing inequality since 1980 is the result of design errors (the ECB's narrow anti-inflation brief) and structural constraints (the lack of fiscal union and democratic oversight), which have prevented an EU-wide wealth tax being considered feasible, rather than deliberate policy. In encouraging the EU to move beyond gestures like a financial transaction tax, and by focusing on inequality of outcome, he is testing its commitment both to socially fair taxation and to democratic accountability.
_____________
Piketty is an empiricist, not an idealist, which ironically makes him more Anglo-Saxon than Continental in his method, despite nods to la longue durée and cultural theory. He observes phenomena, such as r > g, but offers no explanation as to why these arise. For example, why is r (the rate of return to capital) higher than g (the rate of growth)? He focuses on distribution rather than production, hence his work is not a critique of capital in the sense that Marx employed that word, but of simple wealth. Consequently he has little to say about class power, monopolies, or economic imperialism, which leads some critics to conclude that he has not really diverged from the neoclassical tradition: "By, in effect, objectifying capital, considering it apart from the social relationship embedded within it, he marks himself well within the economic mainstream".
This is true, but what Piketty has valuably done is show that the claims of economic theory can be proven or disproven through historical data, which actually places him closer in methodological terms to Marx than the marginalists. Piketty is a reformer, not a revolutionary. He sees no alternative to capital as the motor of the economy, but he is clear that left to its own devices, capitalism will undermine itself through growing inequality. His prescription is institutionalised democracy, but at a time when a corporate tax-avoidance facilitator has been made President of the European Commission, and we have yet to see a single UK-based banker face criminal charges for either negligence or theft, this looks like a big ask.
I read the introduction to Piketty's book and I doubted whether he had ever read Marx, this line makes me even more suspicious:
ReplyDelete"though he disagrees with their apocalyptic prognoses, which he ascribes to historical ignorance of the declining importance of land and the increasing impact of technology"
Piketty claimed during the publicity campaign for the launch of the English version of his book that he hadn't read Kapital, however I suspect he was being disingenuous simply to divert cries of "commie" from US reviewers. A good summary of the evidence that he was a close reader of Marx was provided by John Judis in a New Republic article.
ReplyDeleteThe key divergence is Piketty's belief that technology can sufficiently substitute for labour to keep the rate of profit from declining. This is not quite the same as the orthodox (and commonplace) criticism of Marx, that technology-driven productivity growth has increased the demand for skilled labour over time and led to rising wages - i.e. the story behind the 1945-75 period and the Kuznets Curve.
Piketty's point is that labour's gains from technology over this period were exceptional - the product of wars and depression - and that since 1980 the lion's share has gone to capital in order to restore the historic rate of return and thus r > g. The implication is that the crisis of capitalism will not be simply economic, arising from immiseration and the collapse of demand, but political, as rising inequality causes the owners of capital to revoke democracy.
In this reading the neoliberal hegemony of conventional politics (and consequent popular disenchantment), the democratic deficit of the EU and other international bodies, and the experiments in authoritarian capitalism (the emerging "Eurasian" model) are as symptomatic as the features of secular stagnation.
I think anyone who says Marx was ignorant of the increasing impact of technology must be having a joke, given it's importance to the declining rate of profit and given his polemical work, e.g. Communist Manifesto. I honestly don't even know what is meant by the declining importance of land, but try producing, building anything that doesn't involve the land!
ReplyDeleteThough, again, Marx's work is littered with references to the rise of industrial capitalists, decline of agriculture, arguing that agriculture wasn't the only productive part of the economy etc. Also decline of landowners in relation to capitalists etc.
I think the criticism re increasing demand for skilled Labour represents a linear view of the falling rate of profit, rather than a circular view within a secular trend. What is skilled today becomes relatively unskilled tomorrow. New high value production replaces it and round we go again.
But none of this is new is it? It goes way back, Okishio and before.
In Marx, the substitution of capital for labour leads to a declining rate of profit because the labour portion of the value of a commodity reduces. As profit is the surplus value of labour, if that portion contracts, either the rate of exploitation of labour must increase or profits must shrink.
ReplyDeleteThough new technology may be a way in which this substitution occurs, this does not require an increase in productivity as such, merely that capital replaces labour (at a lower lifetime cost) while at least the same level of output is maintained.
Marx was obviously aware of the ability of technology to improve productivity and thus increase output, but the criticism (by Piketty and others) is that he underestimated the degree to which this would offset the negative impact of capital-labour substitution by creating new forms of demand that in turn redeployed labour into higher value jobs.
Piketty's broader point is that the "equitable" sharing of the gains of productivity increase in the 1914-75 period (i.e. between capital and labour) was the product of social and political pressures and that since 1980 the gains have gone disproportionatelky to capital, producing greater inequality.
The "declining importance of land" relates to Ricardo, not Marx. The former believed that scarcity - i.e. the finite amount of land - would cause rents to rise till they accounted for the bulk of wealth in the economy, thus crowding out industry. What Ricardo failed to see was that improvements in agricultural productivity and transportation (i.e. the importation of food) would result in the rent on land dropping in price over the 19th century.
"Marx was obviously aware of the ability of technology to improve productivity and thus increase output, but the criticism (by Piketty and others) is that he underestimated the degree to which this would offset the negative impact of capital-labour substitution by creating new forms of demand that in turn redeployed labour into higher value jobs."
ReplyDeleteThis is precisely what I think is an erroneous linear view of Marx and not a circular view within a secular trend.
I think Piketty's biggest mistake was that he failed to distinguish between capital and land, as Karl Smith pointed out.
ReplyDelete